top of page

「Reconciling the Dilemmas of Intercultural Consciousness: Constructing Self-Reflexive Agency(異文化間意識のジレンマを調和させる:自己再帰的なエージェンシー[メタ意識]を構築する)」に参加して

 

三河内彰子(東京大学)

 

背景:相対主義の次の段階へ

  今回、山本志都先生より基調講演の報告書の執筆依頼を受け、改めて学会企画の趣旨についておさらいをした。事前のウエブサイトでのお知らせには、2017年の本学会関東地区研究会でDr. Milton Bennett(以下、ベネット先生)を招いた講演会の続きを聞くこと、前回の終わりに相対主義の次の段階について話が及んだことが挙げられていた。この、「相対主義の次の段階」というのは今回の多文化関係学会のテーマである「相対主義のジレンマを超えて」であり、今回の基調講演は、ベネット先生が本テーマに答える形で話を展開し、ジレンマに対峙している参加者一人ひとりが、日々の活動を省み、明日からどう取り組むか考える機会を与えてくださったといえる。 

  本基調講演は単独でも成立するが、前日に開催されたDMISセミナーの続きともいえる。セミナーでは、司会を務められた山本先生曰く、ベネット先生は30年前からすでに同じ構想があって話をされている(始まりは1972年の国際基督教大学での会議、そして1986年に発表)。しかし、当時は異文化間コミュニケーションが相対主義に基づく「適応」という文脈で話された。今「構成主義」が異文化間コミュニケーションで語られるようになったからこそ再度ご招待したと。この言葉が異文化間コミュニケーション論のこの30年の変化を象徴しているように感じた。

  では、相対主義と構成主義では具体的に何がどう違うのだろうか? 現在の社会において異文化間コミュニケーションを構成主義的に捉える意義とは何なのか? どうすれば自己や他者の文化を構成主義的に捉えられるようになるのか、また、教育をどのように行えばよいのか? 様々な疑問を持つ基調講演の参加者に対して、基調講演の副題「自己再帰的なエージェンシー[メタ意識]を構築する(Constructing Self-Reflexive Agency)」が欠かせないポイントとなる。以下の報告でより詳しく触れるが、メタ意識(Metaconsciousness)とはメタレベルで自覚的に自己再帰的になることである。メタ意識を行使することで、文化が人によりつくられたことに気づき、異文化集団に属する人々が互いを再構成しあいながら世界で共存し得る新たな道を構築する可能性が開けることが強調された。

  しかし、相対主義的なアプローチから構成主義的なアプローチをとることは、理論として理解できるとしても、実行するとなるとたやすいことではない。だからこそ、ベネット先生の話は、個々の文化の内容よりも、文化をとらえるために、まずは現実のとらえ方、人の意識や経験などに始まり、凝縮した内容は多岐にわたった。冒頭、この意識、つまり、自己という感覚を持つにいたった自己再帰的意識としての意識が、人類に初めから備わっていたわけではなかったという知見からスタートした。驚いたことに、人類史の大部分を、人はその意味での意識を持たずに生きながらえていたという。これを聴くと、先天的ではないからこそ、意識的になることに注意を払わなければいけないと思わされる。流れるような名講演の後、コメンテーターの鳥飼玖美子先生との問答が、さらに内容を解きほぐし、理解を深化させ、今後とるべき行動へと橋渡しをしてくれた。以下の報告では、講演後の鳥飼先生や聴衆のやり取りを鑑み、ベネット先生ならではの指摘で心に残った点として、構成主義的なアプローチになぜメタ意識が必須であるのかというと点と、そのことで相対主義のジレンマをどう乗り越えられるのかに焦点を絞って報告を行う。

 

相対主義がハイジャックされた

  そもそも、今まさにジレンマを生じさせている相対主義がエドワード・ホール(Edward T. Hall)によって文化比較に持ち込まれた背景こそに、現在に通じる異文化間コミュニケーション(intercultural communication)での困難が存在しており、ひいては他者とお互いの経験を共有するにはどうしたらよいのかという、文化を超えた経験の理論への突破口が期待されていると言える。ベネット先生はホールが異文化間コミュニケーションの創設者の一人であり、それ以前の西洋至上主義の文化比較(前日の話から引用すると、西洋をより文明化した文化と優位付け、唯一の基準とみなすために、他の文化はそれより劣るものとして比較していたことを挙げている)に対して、西洋も含めあらゆる集団に独自のコンテキストが存在し、異なるコンテキストに異なる文化があると理解できる文化相対主義(cultural relativism)という新たな視点をもたらした。

  個々の集団の文化が善し悪しでなく違いとして尊重されて50年、ベネット先生の言葉を借りると、今まさに相対主義は「ハイジャックされている」という。本来は、西洋中心主義によって周辺に追いやられていた存在を尊重するための視点であったが、尊重すればするほど[独立した存在となり]、たとえ相手を憎むような集団であっても、違いは認められなければならないとして権利を主張するようになった。この相対主義の乗っ取りはホールの当初の意図とはかけ離れた状況[集団間での断絶、互いの文化に入っていくようなことができない状況]が生み出された。

  ベネット先生曰く、この状況では独裁的な「私に考えを任せなさい」という指導者にゆだねて絶対主義にもどるか、この世に存在することに意識的になり、意識することに自覚的になることで、新たな道を構築する構成主義的なパラダイムへ前進するかのいずれかの2択だと。ベネット先生は後者のメタ意識を行使することで開ける可能性を強調された。

  つまり、そもそも自己も他者も私たちが生み出した産物であり、その構築のプロセスがあったことにメタレベルで気づくことができると、自分が自己を定義できる自由を得られ、それと同時に、他者は「自分以外」という自分との関係から定義されていることも認識できるようになる。結果、他者の定義にも自身に責任があると自覚できる。その関係性に気づくことで相対主義的の名のもとに自己と他者を分けてしまった異文化間コミュニケーションを見直し、新たな方向性へ進むことができるということなのだ。

  ここでベネット先生は、冒頭で紹介した意識の起源の研究を行ったジュリアン・ジェインズ(Julian Jaynes)の研究から引用して、メタファーとしての私(me)という考えを作り出したことで、meの行為主体となれる私(I)を獲得し、さらに他者に対し人間同士とみなせる視点を得たという点を挙げた。このプロセスは、互いが互いを作りあう関係を生む。ジェインズは、逆に自己を意識しないように抑制することも可能であり、そうすると自己は無意識に陥り、他者の抑圧を引き起こす可能性も示唆している。先ほどの「私に考えをゆだねなさい」という独裁的な指導者は、複雑で困難な社会ではとかく支持されがちであり、実際にそのような指導者が存在するが、考えをゆだねるということは、自己抑制に陥るということなのだ。意識を止めるということは非常に危険な状況をまねくということが強調された。だからこそ、そうならないようにメタ意識を発達させる必要がある。

 

モノに名を与えるという行為は、与えなかったモノにも名を与えているという行為

  自己の定義は、同時に自己と自己以外との間に境界を引いていることを忘れてはならない。ベネット先生はジョージ・スペンサー=ブラウン(George Spencer Brown)から引用し、何かを指し示す時、指し示されたものは図(figure)となり、ただちにその他が地(ground)として背景に回る。つまり、図と地の境界を引くことなしに何かを指し示すことはできないという。例えば、花瓶を認識する際、無意識にその周囲の空間と花瓶との間に境界線を引いていて、花瓶に注目しているからこそ、周囲の空間は背景にまわる。講演会場では、花瓶の背景の空間に注目すると向き合う2人の横顔が浮き上がってくる多義図形が投影され、参加者は花瓶が背景として見えなくなったり、逆にまた花瓶に注目すると横顔が背景になることを体感した。このような花瓶や横顔といった注目している一つのまとまりとそれらの背景部分とをそれぞれ図(figure)と地(ground)と呼ぶ。図地の分化(区別)によってはじめてモノを指し示すことができる。

  ベネット先生は図地の分化からさらに言語の世界に展開してゆく。例として「木」を取り上げて、木を定義すると同時に「木以外のものすべて」(例えば鳥にせよ人にせよ)が区別されることを示す。しかし、その中から一つの側面を名付けて木の対義語とするとしたら、何になるだろうか?と問いかける。そしてこの仕組みがジレンマを生むという。木の対義語が地面ならジレンマとはならないかもしれないが、例えば単一/統一(unity)と多様性(diversity)という分化であれば、ジレンマや衝突を生むことは想像に難くない。つまり、現在世に存在するこの二項対立はそもそも人が作り出したものなのである。

個人的な解釈を交えると、このように分け、分けたことに基づいた経験をし、それを日々個人的にそして集団的に行うことで、さらにその定義が強められたり、弱められて変化して行ったりするといえる。それが繰り返されるうちに人は初めに定義を作りだしたこと自体を忘れ、その定義が外在する所与のものであるかのように認識するようになる。いわゆるバーガーとルックマン(Berger and Luckmann)のいうところの物象化(reification)である。作るプロセスは意識されず、抜け落ちてゆく。これが相対主義のハイジャックをもたらす。逆に物象化されたものを意識的に再構成することで脱物象化する(de-reify)と、二項対立の静的な見方をその二つのモノの間での対話(dialectic)によって動的に和らげる(reconcile)方法を見出すことが期待できる。

  ベネット先生は、これまで異文化間コミュニケーションのトレーニングなどで重宝される文化を氷山にみたてるという比喩も適切ではないと指摘された。会場からは氷山の比喩は生徒にもわかりやすく、多用しているのになぜ?といった反応が見られた。それに対してベネット先生はなじみの実証主義的な比喩だからこそわかりやすいのだと目からうろこの指摘をされた。氷山の比喩は静的で物象化した文化のイメージであり、目指している次の段階がよって立つ構成主義的なパラダイムとは違うのでもう使えないということを意味していると推察する。

  今後は、文化は浮かんでいる静的なモノとしての氷ではなく、構成主義的で動的な渓谷に流れる川で喩えられるという。渓谷は初めからその形をして存在しているのではなく、時をかけて川底を削ることでつくられる。川の勢いや岸でまげられたりするうちに流れる方向が定まる。川自身が日々周りとの相互作用で渓谷を築いている。個人的には、多様な文化が存在しているということは、様々な川があるのと同じで、川が日々流れることで渓谷を築くように、集団の日々の行い、時には個人の行いを通して多様な文化が作られ、変えられたりしてきた、ととらえた。

  文化は何かそこにあるモノを身につけているのではなく(it’s not something we have)、自身が行使し作り上げていっている現在進行形の行為そのものだ(it’s something we are doing)と自覚的に意識できることで、他者の文化もその他者によってつくられていることを共感の下に意識することができる。そのことで、自文化と他文化ひいては自己と他者の存在を、所与のものとして無責任に突き放すことはせず、自分のそして相手の境界の引き方を理解することで、ともに自他の境界を調整しあい、構成主義的に再構成する方向で新たな実行可能な他の経験へと至るというものだ。

  では日々どのような実践をすればよいのだろうか。実際に持続可能な異文化感受性をどのようにもたらすかという問題に関してベネット先生は、これまでは自文化中心の人をDMISでいうところの「防御(defense)」から「最小化(minimization)」へ、そして「最小化」から「受容(acceptance)」や「適応(adaptation)」に変えようとしていたが、それには多大な労力を費やすもので時間の無駄になっていたとし、今後は、私たちのメタ意識の質を高めつつ、既に自文化中心主義から文化相対主義のなかでもこれまでとは違う方向に向こうとし始めている人達に働きかけることが、大きな変革をもたらす力になると指摘された。例えば、学内で既に外国人を相手とすることに積極的な教員にまずワークショップをすると良いと。ベネット先生は実際にその方法でほんの数名の教員から、学期中にそれまで好意的でなかった非常に多くの人を巻き込むことができたそうだ。

 

日本で開催された意義

  今回の基調講演を拝聴し、限られた時間の中でベネット先生が一つ一つの概念をその背景となる理論にさかのぼってかなりの時間を割いて丁寧に話された姿が印象的であった。そこに、日本社会において開催された1つの大きな意義があると感じた。なぜなら、現代社会は絶対主義的な世界観や乗っ取られた相対主義的な世界観が流布し、特に日本では知識(何が知識かということがまず問題だが、ここではそれさえ問うことのない普遍的な知識とでもいっておこう)を積み重ねることで世界観が豊かになるイメージが強い。つまり、何をするにもまずこの普遍的知識をスキルを使って詰め込む必要があるといった見方は根強く、様々な衝突を内蔵する複雑な問題に対して妥当な知識が見いだせないまま打開策を立てられない現状があるからだ。根底の考え方を変えないままで、構成主義的なアプローチを知っても、そちらに舵を切ることは難しい。

  特に会場からの質問や前日のセミナー及び交流会から気づいたが、参加者にはアカデミアや企業など広義の意味で教育現場を持つ方が多く、異文化コミュニケーション×学びという関心事の方が多かったと拝察する。今回の新たなカギとして提示された考え方—他の可能性を経験する―とは、まさに経験を広げる、新たな世界を「学ぶ」ことであり、その点で今後各自の現場でメタ認識を伴うDMISがどのように応用されるか興味深い。個人的なことになるが、前世紀末、構成主義的な学習観がアカデミアで議論となり始めたころ、私は国際基督教大学で教育工学コミュニケーションの分野を専攻し、卒論で教授・学習理論における構成主義の文献研究を行った。大学院の実証研究は心理学をベースに、特に認知科学の分野で行っていたが、観察すればするほど「構成主義的」なプロセスが観え、人の学びは社会的で文脈依存であるという考え方につながり、まさに「日常世界の構築」に興味を持って、ついには文化人類学(なかでも科学人類学)に転向し、実践現場も教室からより多様な人々と専門性が行き交うミュージアムに移すこととなった。あれから四半世紀、今また学校現場にフィールドを戻したところ、まさに、教育界は構成主義的な学習論に基づいた教育へ移行しつつある。一方で、教師はそのような教育を生徒としても教師としても受けておらず、変化に対して非常に大きなジレンマを抱えている。今回の基調講演はその行く手に一筋の光を落としてくれた。

  基調講演の最後に、司会の山本先生が自身の実践の経験を振り返り、時代的に実証主義的なトレーニングから始まり、氷山の比喩を使った実践を経て、最近ようやく構成主義的にやれるようになったとのことでした。そして現在構成主義的アプローチによる大学1,2年生向けの異文化コミュニケーショントレーニングの本をベネット先生、山本先生、石黒武人先生、岡部大祐先生で出す予定だそうだ(2020年に三修社から出版予定)。出版が待ち遠しい。

 

謝辞

  最後に、今回は学会初参加である私を温かく受け入れていただいた皆様に感謝を申し上げます。初参加でしたので、山本先生から基調講演の報告書の依頼があった時には少々驚きましたが、初参加の視点から皆様のお役に立てるのならと、お礼の意も込めて執筆をお引き受け申し上げました。前日のセミナー後の「ハッピーアワー」、「居酒屋交流会with Bennett」でも、初対面ですぐに互いが直面している事象について本音で交流でき、本学会に参加する皆様の異文化間コミュニケーション能力の高さと包容力に背中を押されました。Bennett先生、山本先生をはじめ皆様にあらためて感謝申し上げます。また、基調講演で同時通訳者としてお名前の挙がった故斎藤美津子先生にもこの場を借りて深謝の意を表したいと思います。斉藤先生には四半世紀前、国際基督教大学の一般教養の授業で(今回改めて振り返ると)文脈依存で動的なコミュニケーション論の世界にいざなっていただきました。交流会で他の方からも斎藤先生のお名前が挙がり、自分の世界観のルーツの一つを発見することができました。今後も本学会がホールの意図した異文化間コミュニケーションのスピリッツの下に相対主義のジレンマを超える支えの中心となることを期待します。

Evanoff, Richard (2020). Milton Bennett on Metaconsciousness, Intercultural Communication, and the DMIS.  Japan Society for Multicultural Relations Newsletter 36. 9-13.
Richard Evanoff先生の報告書のPDFはこちらでダウンロードできます ↓
 Full length                     Short lenght (Newsletter ver.)

Milton Bennett博士による基調講演の当日発表資料のダウンロード

Keynote Speech PPT downlaod

Richard Evanoff先生(青山学院大学)と三河内彰子先生(東京大学)による報告書が多文化関係学会ニュースレター第36号に掲載されています。ダウンロード

Newsletter download

Milton Bennett on Metaconsciousness, Intercultural Communication, and the DMIS

 

Richard Evanoff (Aoyama Gakuin University)

 

I first met Milton Bennett at a seminar he gave in Tokyo in October 1992 entitled "Consciousness and Intercultural Communication."  Over the years I've had an opportunity to attend quite a few of Milton's lectures and workshops, and also to learn more from him about consciousness, constructivism, and intercultural communication through private conversations.  I regard Milton as both a teacher and mentor, who has stimulated what has turned out to be an ongoing (never-ending?) research interest in how constructivist ideas might be applied in the field of intercultural communication. 

 

This article is a response to the keynote speech Milton gave at the 19th annual conference of the Japan Society for Multicultural Relations in Tokyo on November 17, 2019 entitled "Reconciling the Dilemmas of Intercultural Consciousness:  Constructing Self-Reflexive Agency (Metaconsciousness)."  The article also attempts to show how Milton's ideas about consciousness correlate with his constructivist approach to intercultural communication, his work on paradigms (Newtonian, Einsteinian, and quantum), and his Developmental Model of Intercultural Sensitivity, topics treated in the workshop Milton conducted on the previous day of the conference (November 16).

 

In developing his own ideas about the relation between consciousness and intercultural communication, Milton takes as his starting point the theory expounded by Julian Jaynes in his classic book, The Origin of Consciousness in the Breakdown of the Bicameral Mind (1990 [1976]).  (I was first exposed to Jaynes' ideas as a college student and played in a rock band at the time, which one of the members, who was also reading Jaynes, named "The Bicameral Mind"!)  Jaynes' thesis is that a higher level of consciousness, which he calls self-reflexive consciousness, is a culturally evolved phenomena which arose only about 3,000 years ago with the fall of numerous civilizations in the Mediterranean and Near Eastern regions (a period known as the Late Bronze Age Collapse).  Prior to that time, it is assumed that humans were conscious in the sense that they were awake (i.e., not asleep, or unconscious) and capable of having sensations (the ability to experience raw sense data), perceptions (the ability to distinguish one object from another), and cognition (the ability to construct categories, linguistic and otherwise, to understand their experience). 

 

What homo sapiens have lacked for most of their 200,000-year history, however, is self-reflexive consciousness, which Jaynes defines as the ability to be aware of the role that we ourselves play in all of these processes.  Rather than simply have sensations, perceptions, and cognitions, we acquire the ability to introspect and reflect on them.  In self-reflexive consciousness we regard ourselves both as subjects, which have the power to act on the things we encounter in experience, and as objects in that we see ourselves as being only one among many other forces that exist in the world.

Before the Bronze Age Collapse, Jaynes contends that human consciousness was pre-reflective.  Humans could think and act, but, lacking a sense of self, had no understanding of the role that themselves played in these processes.  Human psychology was governed by what Jaynes refers to as a bicameral mind, in which the right hemisphere of the brain communicates with the left hemisphere through auditory hallucinations.  (Jaynes regards contemporary cases of schizophrenia as a vestige of the bicameral mind.)  Volition is based not on self-reflective consciousness, but simply on following the "commands" given by these auditory hallucinations.  In support of this claim, Jaynes compiled a considerable amount of evidence drawn from ancient literary sources, including Greek mythology and the Jewish Bible, which shows people acting in accordance with the "voices of the gods" and which Jaynes hypothesizes are in fact communications arising in the bicameral mind.

 

With the collapse of civilizations at the end of the Bronze Age, however, people began to migrate to new areas, thus encountering people who spoke different languages and had different ways of thinking from their own.  The need to communicate interculturally with others about commonly shared experiences led to the emergence of a new form of consciousness, self-reflexive consciousness, which Jaynes regards as a psychological adaptation to an increasingly complex world, brought about by population growth, migration, and, consequently, increased contact among people who previously lived in smaller, more isolated groups.  In short, wider encounters with others led people to question and critically examine their own way of thinking and to develop a new form of consciousness, in which individuals are able to self-reflect on their own ideas and actions, and to change them by rationally considering alternatives, rather than blindly (unreflectively) following the "voices," which they previously took to be commands from the gods.

 

Prior to the development of self-reflexive consciousness, humans lacked a clear sense of "self" as something that exists independently from other people and objects.  The psychological perspective at this point is that anything that exists, exists as part of, rather than separately from, our own experience and, hence, as things that can be more or less treated as we wish, without showing any ethical concern for them.  If we encounter a relatively small number of people outside our own group who are "different" and seem threatening to us, for example, we may deal with the situation by simply killing them (in Jaynes' theory because the voices tell us to).

 

This strategy becomes maladaptive, however, once we find ourselves surrounded by an ever-growing number of people (as occurred following the Bronze Age Collapse), since we recognize that the chances of us being killed by these numerous others are much greater than the chances of us killing them first.  Self-reflexive consciousness thus evolves a more or less "live and let live" attitude, which insures our own self-preservation by psychologically acknowledging the independent existence of both ourselves and others.  In other words, another person no longer exists simply as part of my own experience, but also externally as a genuine "other" distinct from myself.

 

With the appearance of self-reflexive consciousness, Jaynes contends that the bicameral mind began to "break down."  People ceased having auditory hallucinations or at least stopped believing that these hallucinations came from the gods.  The new social situation required people to cooperate with, rather than kill, each other.  In the process of figuring out how to communicate with others despite not sharing a common language, self-reflexive consciousness emerges, which enables people to introspect and rationally reflect on their experiences, and thus better coordinate their activities with each other.  Although Jaynes' theory of the bicameral mind remains controversial, it has gained qualified support from a variety of scholars, including the philosopher, Daniel Dennett (1986), and the evolutionary biologist, Richard Dawkins (2007), as one plausible, if not fully proven, hypothesis about how higher levels of consciousness might have evolved among humans.

 

Fortunately Milton's own treatment of consciousness can be established independently of Jaynes' theory, since, as mentioned previously, Milton uses Jaynes only as a starting point and not as the foundation for his own views.  The key, and relatively uncontentious claims, are, first, that humans have indeed evolved higher forms of consciousness, which enable us to critically reflect on our experience as detached observers, as attested to by recent research on metacognition, i.e., knowing about knowing, thinking about thinking, being aware of one's awareness (for a comprehensive overview see Dunlosky and Metcalfe 2009).  The second claim, which should be familiar to most researchers in the field of intercultural communication, is that interactions with others, particularly people from other cultures, stimulates self-conscious reflection since such encounters oblige us to admit that our own views about life and the world can be challenged by the differing views of others.

 

Self-reflexive consciousness appears once we are able to differentiate between ourselves as an "I" and other persons and objects as "not-I."  The "I" is not a substantival "thing" (mind, psyche, or soul) that is ontologically distinct from our bodies as Descartes and other philosophers have supposed, but rather a psychological construct we invent to capture the sense that we as individuals exist independently from the things that surround us.  In self-reflexive consciousness the "I" becomes aware of the role that it plays in constructing its views about life.  We do not simply follow what the gods (or voices) tell us to do, but begin to think for ourselves and to arrive at our own ideas about how to relate both to the world and to others in society.

In the process of constructing a distinction between self and others, we encounter a paradox, however, which is that the self can be simultaneously seen as a subject which experiences and an object which is experienced (the "I" is also a "me").  It is precisely the ability to experience ourselves as objects which allows us to develop self-reflexive consciousness, because now we are able to take a step back from ourselves and to look at ourselves from a point of view which is in a sense external to ourselves as experiencing subjects.

 

Moreover, in the process of recognizing that we ourselves are both subjects and objects, we come to recognize that other people are also both subjects and objects.  In other words, we become aware that others are not simply objects that we, as subjects, experience, but that they themselves are also subjects who experience us as objects.  As a result we are able to develop what psychologists refer to as a theory of mind, i.e., the ability to recognize that other people have minds that are similar to but independent from our own.

 

In dealing with what we take to be the "objects" of our experience (both physical objects and other persons), we make what Milton refers to as figure–ground distinctions.  We distinguish, for example, between the "tree" and the "forest" that surrounds it or, more generally between that which we direct our attention towards as figure and the relatively unnoticed things which surround it as ground.  Without the ability to make figure–ground distinctions, the world would appear to us as an undifferentiated slush—what the philosopher, William James, called a "blooming, buzzing confusion" (1950 [1890], p. 488).

 

Distinctions between figure and ground are what make language possible, because we are able to sort the world into "things" which we can then label and categorize.  A word such as snowflake is a term we create to talk about objects that we psychologically categorize as being in some sense "similar," even though they may in fact be quite different from each other (no two snowflakes are exactly alike).  For Jaynes, the ability to use metaphors greatly extends the human capacity for categorization because they allow us to make the move from concrete to abstract thinking.  We may, for example, use the word head concretely to refer to the "thing" at the top of our bodies, but we may also use it metaphorically, i.e., abstractly, to refer to such "things" as the "head of an army, table, page, bed, ship, household, or nail…" (Jaynes 1990, p. 49).  Jaynes contends that the shift from concrete to metaphorical/abstract thinking is, in part, what enabled humans to evolve higher levels of consciousness (for a more philosophical treatment of metaphors, see Lakoff and Johnson 1980).

 

From a constructivist perspective all categories—constructs in George Kelly's (1955) terminology, schema in Piaget's (1985)—linguistic and otherwise, are psychological creations, even though the reality they purport to describe may indeed have an independent existence apart from our awareness of it.  (In numerous conversations I've had with Milton on this point, he always insists that constructivism is not a form of solipsism—the idealistic view that reality exists only "inside the head.")  Nonetheless, we may adopt a reified view of the constructs we use for describing the world if we unwittingly regard them as being "given" to us in some way by external reality rather than as creations of our own minds.  Milton often references Berger and Luckmann's classic book, The Social Construction of Reality (1966), to drive home this point.  In other words, while whatever is physically "real" is mind-independent, constructs are not.

 

Unlike physical reality, social reality has no external reality apart from human consciousness.  Social phenomena, such as laws, national borders, and the value of money, have no objective existence in the absence of human consciousness.  Cultural norms as well exist nowhere in the physical world but are rather brought into being (constructed) through human psychological processes.  Culture, then, is simply a set of norms intersubjectively shared in varying degrees by the members of a given social group.  Moreover, once these norms disappear from consciousness, they cease to exist.  In Anthony Giddens' (1984) structuration theory, social realities continue to exist only to the extent that they are reproduced intersubjectively by the individual members of a given society.

Milton similarly resolves what is known as the structure–agency debate by seeing social structures as being maintained through the agency of individuals.  In a conversation I had with him just prior to his keynote speech, Milton suggested that a social institution, such as democracy, ceases to exist once people lose faith in it and stop voting.  Nonetheless, it is not uncommon for people to adopt a reified view of social reality by thinking that cultural norms are given to us by nature rather than being socially constructed (e.g., humans are by nature competitive, so capitalism is the best economic system vs. humans are by nature cooperative, so communism is the best economic system).

 

Constructivists contend to the contrary that if social realities are constructed through communicative practices, then they can also be dismantled and reconstructed.  This process of reconstruction is possible precisely because humans are capable of engaging in self-reflective thought.  Even though each of us is socialized into accepting the cultural norms of the societies we are brought up in, we are never beholden to those norms.  Rather, we can think critically and imaginatively about whether we wish to maintain existing cultural norms or to radically change them.  Since cultural norms are just ideas in the head, they can be freely criticized both within and between cultures.  While we should always avoid criticizing the people of a culture which is different from our own, it is still possible to critically (and constructively) evaluate their norms in the same way that it is possible to critically evaluate the norms of our own culture.

 

What enables us to engage in critical reflection is metaconsciousness, which is simply the ability to be conscious of our own consciousness.  Not only do we become aware of the role that we play in constructing our ideas about the physical world and social reality (self-reflexive consciousness), but we become aware that we ourselves have the ability to control this process (metaconsciousness).  In other words, it is metaconsciousness that allows us to recognize our own powers of agency.  If we don't like the ideas and norms we have constructed on the basis of self-reflexive consciousness, we are able to question, challenge, refine, and indeed change them through the use of metaconsciousness.

 

At the level of self-reflexive consciousness, we recognize that others have an independent existence from ourselves and are, therefore, autonomous in the same way that we ourselves are.  That is, we see that other individuals are capable of making their own judgments about how their ideas are or should be constructed, and these may differ from the judgments we make about our own constructions.  Thus, there may be significant differences between how the members of one cultural group construct their views of the physical world and social reality and how the members of other cultural groups construct their own views.

 

As a result, we may be inclined to adopt the cultural relativist position that, in the interest of avoiding conflict with people from other cultures whose views are different from our own, we should simply accept and respect all cultures just as they are.  This stance is widely accepted among practitioners in the field of intercultural communication and has served us well in the past, but nonetheless, as Milton contends, has severe limitations.  The main problem is that cultural relativism easily leads to the view that one person's opinion is as good as another's, a view which has been coopted in recent times by those who wish maintain their own position on any given issue without giving persuasive arguments in its defense.  Some people think global warming exists; others don't.  Since no objective arguments can be made in favor of one opinion over the other, "truth" is simply a matter of whatever we think it is.

 

While cultural relativism is often regarded as a "progressive" point of view, since it adopts the "live and let live" mentality of self-reflexive consciousness, it is in fact highly regressive and tradition-bound.  Precisely because cultural relativism goes no further than to contend that different cultures construct their ideas differently, it fails to consider how people from different cultures might constructively critique their existing cultural norms and imaginatively create entire new norms that might enable them to cooperate more effectively with each other.

 

Milton criticizes both the tendency of modernism, based on a Newtonian worldview, to think that there are certain absolutes which should be universally adopted by all cultures since they are part of objective reality or "nature" and hence not subject to cultural variation, and the tendency of postmodernism, based on an Einsteinian worldview, to see any and all ideas as being subjective/intersubjective and thus relative to the cultural context in which they appear.  Milton's favored approach is constructivism, which concurs with the quantum view that observers are themselves part of the reality they are observing (Bennett 2005; 2013; for an independent treatment of these perspectives, see Evanoff 2004; 2006).  That is, we do not simply passively observe the world and other people but actively engage ourselves with them.  Constructions are not simply a matter of subjective opinion, but are created through the interactions we have both with the world and with others in society.

 

Jaynes' concept of self-reflexive consciousness only takes us, as it were, to the postmodern level.  We recognize that each of us actively constructs our view of the world and social reality, both individually and collectively as members of a given culture.  We further recognize that others are capable, both individually and collectively of constructing their own distinct ideas about physical and social reality.  It may be concluded from the standpoint of self-reflexive consciousness that since there are no absolutes (in the Newtonian sense), we should therefore simply accept and respect different cultures as they are, since any ideas that a given individual may have are only understandable in the context of the particular culture that person is a member of (as the Einsteinian worldview suggests) and it is impossible to critique the point of view of any other culture except from the perspective of one's own culture.

 

The next step, in Milton's view, is for us to move from a relativist position based on self-reflexive consciousness to a constructivist perspective based on metaconsciousness.  In the same way that self-reflexive consciousness was a suitable evolutionary adaptation to changing circumstances in the past, when cultural differences needed to be recognized, metaconsicouness is an appropriate evolutionary adaptation to the present, when differences need to be not simply recognized but also negotiated.

 

In self-reflexive consciousness the "I" recognizes itself as distinct from the "not-I" (oneself and others).  Moreover, as the "I" becomes cognizant of the role that it plays in constructing its views of the world, it also becomes aware that others, particularly people from different cultures, construct their own views, which may be different from one's own, a perspective which leads effortlessly to the notion that all ideas, values, and norms are relative to the particular social contexts in which they appear.

 

In metaconsciousness, however, the "I" is aware not only that it and other "I's" are responsible for constructing their own views of the world (self-reflexive consciousness), but also that each "I" has the ability to direct and control its own constructions (metaconsciousness).  Whereas self-reflexive consciousness always remains inside the process of construct formation, metaconsciousness allows us to step outside the process and to critically examine it from a detached point of view.  Consider the difference between baking a cake and being aware that we are following a recipe that someone (either ourselves or others) has at some point in time constructed (self-reflexive consciousness) and being aware that if we don't like the recipe we can change it (metaconsciousness).

 

To the extent that I am able to critically examine my own constructive activities from a meta-perspective, I realize not only that I am engaging in constructive activity as such, but also that I am "in charge" of directing my own thoughts and behavior.  It is metaconsciousness, then, which leads us to a recognition of what Milton refers to as our own agency.  Moreover, it is this acquired sense of agency that allows us to take ethical responsibility for how we think and act.

 

Milton's theory of metaconsciousness can be (roughly) mapped onto his Developmental Model of Intercultural Sensitivity (DMIS) (Bennett 1993; 2013; see also Yamamoto 1996).  As with all stage models of psychological development, the empirical question of whether people actually move through each of the stages in the order given (sometimes they do and sometimes they don't) is separate from the philosophical question of whether the stages represent a logical progression moving from simple to more complex levels of experience.  In the case of Milton's DMIS, increases in one's experience of cultural difference lead to increases in cultural sensitivity, which in turns lead to increases in consciousness.

 

The most basic ethnocentric stage in Milton's model, the stage of denial, correlates more or less to a pre-reflexive level of consciousness.  Individuals are conditioned through socialization processes to unquestioningly accept the norms of the particular cultures they grow up in.  They typically hold the reified view that one's own cultural norms are simply "the way things are."  Culture is as "natural" to them as the air they breathe and they have no awareness (consciousness) that things could be otherwise.

 

The bubble of one's own cultural experience is pricked the moment that individuals are exposed to cultures which are different from their own.  At the second ethnocentric stage, defense, difference is recognized, but it is thought that only one of the competing sets of cultural norms can be "right" or "correct."  This stage may be compared to the stage of intellectual and ethical development referred to by Perry (1970) as dualism.  (In the remainder of this article I will follow the simplified version of Perry's model used by Milton in his lectures.)  Most people generally assume that the norms of their own culture are superior to those of other cultures, although in reversal individuals may come to think that the norms of another culture are superior to their own.  Individuals at the stage of defense may be tempted to think that their own cultural norms should be imposed on other cultures (cultural imperialism) or, in the case of reversal, that their own culture should assimilate the norms of the other culture.

 

The third ethnocentric stage of intercultural sensitivity, minimization, adopts the view that any cultural differences we encounter can only be superficial since underneath people are basically the "same."  This stance is often grounded on an essentialist view of human nature (there are certain fundamental characteristics which are shared by all humans) and often engages in the quixotic attempt to identify "core" human beliefs, values, and norms regarded as absolute, in that they do not change over time, and universal, since they are (or should be) adopted by everyone (similar to the Newtonian worldview).  Perennial philosophy and the search for "cultural universals" in anthropology are examples, since both have a tendency to focus almost exclusive attention on cultural similarities while minimizing cultural differences.  Consciousness at both the defense and minimization stages is reflective, but not yet self-reflexive, because it still holds the reified view that cultural norms are something to be discovered rather than something we create.

 

With the general shift from an ethnocentric to an ethnorelative perspective, however, consciousness acquires self-reflexivity once we recognize that there is more than one way of understanding the world and our place in it, and thus become aware of the constructed nature of both our own cultural norms and those of other cultures.  At the fourth stage of the DMIS, acceptance, we simply accept cultural differences as they are, without trying to modify or improve them.  Similar to the stage of multiplicity in Perry's model, we acknowledge that there is no one "true" or "correct" culture but rather regard all cultural norms as equally valid.  While we have broken out of our own cultural molds, so to speak, we may also experience confusion (anomie) at this stage since we are unsure about which cultural norms we should commit ourselves to.  Nonetheless, trying to figure out which norms we should accept and which we should reject is what starts us down the road of self-reflexive consciousness.  At this point we may see that the acceptance of cultural diversity provides us with a means for getting along with others in multicultural situations, although we have not yet developed the more critical perspective of metaconsciousness, which allows us to actively critique existing cultural forms in both our own and another culture, and to creatively imagine new ones.

 

The ability to engage in such critiques only begins to develop during the fifth stage of the DMIS:  adaptation.  An immature view of adaptation sees it simply as the attempt to assimilate oneself to the norms of another culture, sometimes by crudely imitating the thoughts and behavior of people from that culture.  The assimilationist approach to adaptation is best expressed in the proverb, "When in Rome do as the Romans do," and also corresponds to the stage of contextual relativism in Perry's model.  We begin to see all constructions as valid only within the particular culture in which they are formulated and may be inclined to adopt the relativist view that since any criticisms we may make of another culture can only be made from a standpoint within our culture, all cultures should simply be respected as they are.

 

While there are certainly occasions in which it is best to simply follow the norms of another culture out of respect (I always take my shoes off when I enter a Japanese house even though that is not a norm in my own culture), it soon becomes apparent that it is impossible for persons to completely give up their own culture and thoroughly assimilate themselves to a different culture.  Rather quickly sojourners typically begin to engage in a more selective approach, in which they adopt some of the norms of the other culture while rejecting others.  Simultaneously they may come to have a greater appreciation for their original culture and thus wish to selectively retain some elements of their own culture while rejecting others.

 

Now, what exactly is it that enables us to engage in this process of selectivity?  The answer, as suggested by Milton, is metaconsciousness, which allows us to step outside the perspective of our own respective cultures and to consider the views of people whose cultures are different from our own (this, indeed, is the key point of ethnorelativism).  At the same time, however, we do not simply accept or adapt ourselves to all the norms of another culture.  Rather, using metaconsciousness, we begin to critically reflect on the norms of other cultures as part of the process of selectively deciding which aspects of the other culture we wish to adopt as our own.  The process is essentially dialectical in the Hegelian sense, since it involves determining which aspects of our own culture (the thesis) we wish to retain and which we wish to reject, and which aspects of the other culture (the antithesis) we wish to adopt and which we wish to reject.  This dialectical process actually commences the very moment that cultural differences are recognized (following the denial stage) and is continuous throughout each of the stages on the DMIS continuum.

 

The problem here is that the conflict between the thesis and antithesis (my culture and yours) may lead to something akin to a "split personality" if tensions between the two cannot be reconciled within one's own mind.  Yoshikawa's (1987) double-swing model notes, but does not fully resolve this dilemma, by suggesting that individuals shift between cultural frames depending the cultural group they are interacting with (I act like a Japanese when I'm with Japanese people and like an American when I'm with Americans).  To avoid simply swinging back and forth between opposing cultural norms, metaconsciousness may be used as a way to construct new ways of thinking which combine what we take to be positive aspects of both cultures, while rejecting the negative aspects.  This results in a Hegelian synthesis of what were originally regarded as two sets of conflicting cultural norms.  In Milton's DMIS, this stage is referred to as integration.  The term third-culture building (Casmir 1993) may also be used to designate a process in which we, not only as children but also adults, are able to integrate elements of our own (first) culture with those of another (second) culture to create a new (third) culture.

 

There are two points I would like to add as refinements to Milton's model (for a fuller treatment of both points, see Evanoff 2009).  The first is that the DMIS is primarily concerned with integration at the psychological level:  how do individuals reconcile cultural differences within their own way of thinking?  Integration can also be regarded, however, as a social process in which people from different cultures negotiate differences between themselves by engaging in intercultural dialogue with each other.  Integration can also be considered at the formal level as the attempt to reconcile conflicting points of view into a more comprehensive conceptual framework, which may be able to overcome cultural and ideological divisions among people.  While metaconsciousness is indeed an individual psychological phenomenon, it may nonetheless be effectively employed at each of these levels.

 

Second, it seems possible for a seventh stage to be included in the DMIS, namely a generative stage, which goes beyond simply combining elements of existing cultures in novel ways (as occurs at the integration stage) to the active construction of entirely new forms of culture that never existed before.  Humans are confronted with a wide range of emergent problems that we did not have to face in the past and which cannot be addressed simply by appealing to traditional cultural norms, whether alone or in combination with each other.  Global warming, for example, cannot be effectively dealt with simply by constructing an ecological ethic on the basis of existing cultural norms, but rather requires a complete rethinking of how our cultures in general and our economies in particular relate to the environment.  Fortunately, in addition to its ability to critically examine existing cultural forms, metaconsciousness also has an imaginative side, which may be employed to generate entirely new forms of society and culture to deal with such problems.  Empirical research in the field of intercultural communication, which is confined by its own disciplinary boundaries to describing existing forms of culture, can be profitably supplemented with more normative, philosophical studies aimed at imagining solutions to problems that are mutually faced by people from different cultures (Evanoff 2015).

 

References

Bennett, Milton J. (1993).  "Towards Ethnorelativism:  A Developmental Model of Intercultural Sensitivity."  In Education for the Intercultural Experience (pp. 21–71).    Ed. Michael Paige.  Yarmouth:  Intercultural Press.  Available on the Intercultural Development Research Institute website at <https://www.idrinstitute.org/dmis>.

______ (2005).  "Paradigmatic Assumptions of Intercultural Communication."  Hillsboro:  IDRInstitute.  Available on the Intercultural Development Research Institute website at <https://www.idrinstitute.org/wp-content/uploads/2018/02/Paradigmatic-Assumptions.pdf>.

______ (2013).  Basic Concepts of Intercultural Communication:  Paradigms, Principles, and Practices.  2nd ed.  Boston:  Intercultural Press.

Berger, Peter and Thomas Luckmann (1966).  The Social Construction of Reality.  Garden City:  Doubleday.

Casmir, Fred L. (1993).  "Third Culture Building:  A Paradigm Shift for International and Intercultural Communication."  In Communication Yearbook (vol. 16, pp. 407–428).  Ed. Stanley A. Deetz.  Newbury Park:  Sage.

Dawkins, Richard (2007).  The God Delusion.  London:  Black Swan.

Dennett, Daniel C. (1986).  "Julian Jaynes' Software Archaeology."  Canadian Psychology 27(2):149–154. 

Dunlosky, John and Janet Metcalfe (2009).  Metacognition.  Los Angeles:  Sage.

Evanoff, Richard (2004).  "Universalist, Relativist, and Constructivist Approaches to Intercultural Ethics."  International Journal of Intercultural Relations 28(5):439–458.

______ (2006).  "Intercultural Ethics:  A Constructivist Approach."  Journal of Intercultural Communication 9:89–102.  Available on the Intercultural Development Research Institute website at <https://www.idrinstitute.org/wp-content/uploads/2018/02/Evanoff-Intercultural_Ethics.pdf>.

______ (2009).  "Integration in Intercultural Ethics."  In Intercultural Communication:  A Reader (pp. 447–459).  Ed. Larry A. Samovar, Richard E. Porter, and Edwin R. McDaniel.  12th edition.  Boston:  Wadsworth Cengage Learning.

______ (2015).  "Intercultural Philosophy and Constructivist Dialogue on Cross-Cultural Norms."  Delti 4:77­–89.

Giddens, Anthony (1984).  The Constitution of Society.  Cambridge:  Polity.

James, William (1950 [1890]).  The Principles of Psychology.  Vol. 1.  New York:  Dover.

Jaynes, Julian (1990 [1976]).  The Origin of Consciousness in the Breakdown of the Bicameral Mind.  Boston:  Houghton Mifflin.

Kelly, George A. (1955).  The Psychology of Personal Constructs.  New York:  Norton.

Lakoff, George and Mark Johnson (1980).  Metaphors We Live By.  Chicago:  University of Chicago Press.

Perry, William (1970).  Forms of Intellectual and Ethical Development in the College Years.  New York:  Holt, Rinehart, and Winston.

Piaget, Jean (1985).  The Equilibration of Cognitive Structures:  The Central Problem of Intellectual Development.  Trans. Terrance Brown and Kishore Julian Thampy.  Chicago:  University of Chicago Press.

Yamamoto, Shizu (1996).  "A Theoretical Grounding of the Intercultural Sensitivity Model."  Contexture 14:67–88.  (Osaka:  Saitama Institute of Technology).  Available on the Intercultural Development Research Institute website at <https://www.idrinstitute.org/wp-content/uploads/2019/02/A-Theoretical-Grounding-of-the-Intercultural-Sensitivity-Model-1.pdf>.

Yoshikawa, Muneo Jay (1987).  "The Double-Swing Model of Intercultural Communication between the East and the West."  In Communication Theory:  Eastern and Western Perspectives (pp. 319–329).  San Diego:  Academic Press.

 

6T3A5929a.jpg
リチャード・エバノフ先生
素晴らしいご報告書を
ありがとうございました!
Thank you !
bottom of page